Lectures
- 1. Introduction
- 2. Hedonism
- 3. Desire satisfaction and the good
- 4. Objective goods
- 5. Immortality
- 6. Three moral theories
- 7. Film: "The Global Banquet: Politics of Food"
- 8. Film: "Skin Deep"
- 9. Animal rights
- 10. Consuming animals
- 11. The value of nature
- 12. Environmentalism
- 13. The distant needy
- 14. Famine relief
- 15. Addressing structural injustice
- 16. Racism: attitudes and structures
- 17. Affirmative action
- 18. Racist speech
- 19. Hate speech
- 20. Free speech and pornography
- 21. Pornography and equality
- 22. Film: "Tying the Knot"
- 23. Sexual morality
- 24. Homosexuality
- 25. Gay and lesbian marriage
Moral Problems and the Good Life - Lecture 9
Lecture 9 - Animal rights
The Moral Community
Two sets of questions:
1) What is a moral community, and who is in our moral community? OR: What beings have moral
status and so should be treated as having equal moral worth? (What does it mean to treat
something as having "equal moral worth"?)
2) How should members of our moral community treat things outside of our moral community? Are there any things outside of our moral community that have value (intrinsic? instrumental? other?) and should be treated with respect?
• I. Rights and the Moral Community
The notion of "rights" usually applies to those within our moral community. We are obligated to treat
those things or individuals within our moral community with a kind of respect that honors their moral
status.
On what basis do things qualify as belonging in (a), i.e., the inner circle? One possible answer (See, e.g., Michael Allen Fox, "The Moral Community," in Hugh LaFollette, Ethics in Practice. Oxford 2006.): full autonomy, such as: critical self-awareness; the ability to manipulate complex concepts and to use a sophisticated language...; and the capacity to reflect, plan, deliberate, choose, an accept responsibility for acting (182). These belong in (a) because they are capable of being full moral agents. Animals are not included. Space aliens with sufficient cognitive capacities might be included. What about fetuses? Infants? Brain damaged adults? Human beings in comas or seriously senile? Fox says: Let us say, then, that although underdeveloped or deficient humans are also, like animals, not full members of the moral community because they lack autonomy, they must nevertheless fall within the most immediate extension of the moral community and as such are subject to its protection. (Fox, 189) So it seems that on his view, they fall within (b). Why? It cannot be because they will develop the full range of capacities distinctive of autonomy, because they may not. Rather, he suggests sympathy with the idea that we are connected to them via a "chain of love and concern" (189). But isn't the question not whether we happen to feel more concern for a suffering infant or brain damaged adult than a suffering puppy or elephant, but whether we should feel more concern for one than the other? And what are our moral responsibilities to things outside of our moral community? Is it OK simply to destroy creatures who lack autonomy, or cause them to suffer? Is it OK simply to destroy ecosystems? How should we understand the wrong of destroying valuable things? In contrast to Fox, Singer seems to suggest that the boundaries of our moral community should be drawn according to the extent that the individuals in question can suffer, i.e., experience pain and pleasure. Those beings with more complex capacities for pain and suffering lie within (a), and those with less complex capacities lie in (b) and (c).
• II. What obligations do we have towards things of value?
Recall the distinction between instrumental goods and intrinsic goods: something is instrumentally good
if it is good as a means to some other good. Intrinsic goods are good in themselves. We can now begin to
clarify this further. Whether or not something is an instrumental good is a matter of how we value it: do
we value it as a means to something else, or do we value it for its own sake? A heuristic to determine
whether you value something instrumentally is to consider: would you still value it even if it didn't have
the same effects?
Intrinsic goods are better contrasted not with instrumental goods, but extrinsic goods. An extrinsic good is valuable because of its relation to something else as opposed to some fact about it. A heuristic to bring out the contrast is the "isolation test": X is intrinsically valuable just in case it would be valuable even in a world where there was nothing else. Examples (some controversial, but the point is to get the idea, not to agree):
Valued instrumentally: vaccinations
Extrinsically good: photo of Gandhi, Einstein's letters
• Conferred and unconferred goods
We now need another distinction between conferred and unconferred goods. Something has conferred
value just in case it is valuable because someone values it. Something has unconferred value just in case it
has value regardless of whether or not it is valued. Note that if things have conferred value, they are
extrinsically valuable. (Can things be extrinsically valuable without that value being conferred?)
Value conferred: money Questions: i) Is anything intrinsically good that is not good for humans? ii) Is all value conferred (by humans)? Definitions and possible principles: Pro Tanto obligation ("only so far" obligation): an obligation that may be overridden by other moral considerations. Intrinsic value principle (recall Kant's Principle of Humanity): Things with intrinsic value should be valued for their own sake and not merely instrumentally. Possible principle: Because of their intrinsic value, we have a prima facie obligation to avoid destroying animals, and healthy ecosystems (of a certain degree of complexity)...and what else?...independent of human attitudes towards them or good they may bring to humans.
• III. Equal consideration
Pain, suffering, and death, are generally agreed to be bad things. From a moral point of view it seems that
the badness of pain doesn't depend on who feels it; its badness resides simply in what it feels like. As
Peter Singer says, "How bad a pain is depends on how intense it is and how long it lasts...pains of the
same intens
ity and duration are equally bad..." (from original). Although it is morally permissible-- perhaps even morally required--for me to respond to my daughter's pain differently from a stranger's pain, in cases where I don't have such special duties it seems that I should be impartial and respond simply to the badness of the situation. Claims of equality are not descriptive claims about equal talents, abilities, and the like. Rather, they are claims about moral worth and respect. It is clear that the Declaration of Independence is not asserting that "all men are created [with] equal [intelligence...etc.]," for that would be clearly false. Instead it is claiming that the well-being of each person is of equal value. (480) Happiness is happiness, pain is pain, regardless of whose it is. The idea that each person's welfare is of equal value does not entail, however, that we must be treated the same way. Valuing their welfare equally will require recognizing their differences and providing differential treatment. A system of "formal equality" is one that guarantees equal treatment. A system of "substantive equality" aims to demonstrate equal respect for everyone's welfare. In order to achieve substantive equality, something must be done to address different needs even though it involves different treatment. Example: access to the break room.
• IV. Animal suffering
With these points in place, we can now turn to Singer's argument supporting the equality of animals.
1. The capacity to suffer (experience pleasure and pain) is the basis for equal consideration in a moral
community. (481) Objections:
· It is difficult to compare the suffering of non-human animals and the suffering of humans, since we
can't talk to non-human animals. Might it be that the happiness brought about by wearing a fur coat
outweighs the suffering of the animals that were killed to make it?
• V. Animal killing
Singer acknowledges that the question of killing animals is more complicated. Human lives are very
different from non-human lives. Humans are capable of self-awareness, planning, complex social
relationships, and the like, that make for goods over the span of a life that are not available to non-human
animals. To kill a human is to put an end to distinctively human goods. So killing a human is worse than
killing an animal, and if there is pressure to choose between killing a human and killing a non-human
animal, it would usually be permissible to kill the animal.
Acknowledging this, however, Singer maintains: To avoid speciesism we must allow that beings who are similar in all relevant respects have a similar right to life--and mere membership in our own biological species cannot be a morally relevant criterion for this right. (626-27) So Singer is willing to hold that killing animals should be treated as comparable to killing babies with serious birth defects or killing "someone in a state of advanced senility". (627) Whether or not that is ever justified is a question he chooses not to answer here. In other words, Singer thinks that his approach to animal rights helps us understand that the moral boundary we should respect is not the boundary between humans and non-humans, but between beings with certain capacities and others without them. Some humans lack the full spectrum of normal human capacities; some non-human animals have capacities that significantly overlap ours. The capacity to suffer is one that unites us with non-humans in a moral community; complex intellectual and emotional capacities divide humans into smaller sub-groups. As Singer sees it, these broader and narrower groupings are the morally relevant ones. Instead most of us are making the serious error of treating the boundaries of our species as the boundaries of our moral community.
Questions:
· Is it permissible to kill plants? Must we all become fruitarians?
Prof. Sally Haslanger
24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life, Fall 2008 (Massachusetts Institute of Technology: MIT OpenCourseWare) http://ocw.mit.edu Date accessed: 2009-07-28 License: Creative Commons BY-NC-SA |
Lecture Material
To view the lecture material accompanying this lecture in a new window, please click the button below. If necessary, use the vertical or horizontal scrollbar in the new window to view more of the material or you can resize the window.
To download the above lecture material use this link. (Right-click and select Save Target As or Save Link As.)